Skip to main content

Can Peto’s paradox be used as the null hypothesis to identify the role of evolution in natural resistance to cancer? A critical review

Abstract

Background

Carcinogenesis affects not only humans but almost all metazoan species. Understanding the rules driving the occurrence of cancers in the wild is currently expected to provide crucial insights into identifying how some species may have evolved efficient cancer resistance mechanisms. Recently the absence of correlation across species between cancer prevalence and body size (coined as Peto’s paradox) has attracted a lot of attention. Indeed, the disparity between this null hypothesis, where every cell is assumed to have an identical probability to undergo malignant transformation, and empirical observations is particularly important to understand, due to the fact that it could facilitate the identification of animal species that are more resistant to carcinogenesis than expected. Moreover it would open up ways to identify the selective pressures that may be involved in cancer resistance. However, Peto’s paradox relies on several questionable assumptions, complicating the interpretation of the divergence between expected and observed cancer incidences.

Discussions

Here we review and challenge the different hypotheses on which this paradox relies on with the aim of identifying how this null hypothesis could be better estimated in order to provide a standard protocol to study the deviation between theoretical/theoretically predicted and observed cancer incidence. We show that due to the disproportion and restricted nature of available data on animal cancers, applying Peto’s hypotheses at species level could result in erroneous conclusions, and actually assume the existence of a paradox. Instead of using species level comparisons, we propose an organ level approach to be a more accurate test of Peto’s assumptions.

Summary

The accuracy of Peto’s paradox assumptions are rarely valid and/or quantifiable, suggesting the need to reconsider the use of Peto’s paradox as a null hypothesis in identifying the influence of natural selection on cancer resistance mechanisms.

Peer Review reports

Background

In the constant search for novel therapeutic strategies against cancer, identifying and understanding natural tumor suppressor mechanisms could provide promising alternative avenues; nevertheless this area of research still remains in its infancy [15]. While the human genome is being extensively explored for genes involved in cancer initiation or progression [68], analysis of cancer resistance in wildlife could also identify additional, previously overlooked, tumor suppressor mechanisms [9], and concomitantly contribute to deciphering the underlying selective forces and evolutionary processes [10]. While almost all metazoan species are affected by cancer [1114] (Fig. 1), some animal species or individuals are more at cancer risk than others [4, 9, 15, 16], suggesting that resistance mechanisms have independently evolved in distant lineages [3, 4, 17]. For example, while rodents demonstrate a characteristically high prevalence of malignancies [18], cancer has never been observed in naked mole-rats (Heterocephalus glaber) [19], not even in captivity, indicating that this species has developed efficient tumor suppressor mechanisms during its evolution.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Predicted cancer risk at different scales: between different species, between individuals from the same population, between organs in an individual, and between cell types (purple cells are more at risk). From top to bottom: the different shapes represent theoretical species and variation in cancer prevalence; the red crosses represent different indivuals of the same species and the number of tumors (e.g. centenarians in a population). The third row illustrates the expected variation of tumor numbers among different organs (e.g. small intestine and large intestine). The last row shows variation in cancer risk at the cellular scale (e.g. stem cells and differentiated cells).

During the quest of identifying species with efficient cancer resistance, a simplistic approach can be employed [2022]. Starting from the assumptions that carcinogenesis progresses via accumulation of mutations, and that every cell division has an identical probability to generate these mutations, a simple prediction can be drawn: large/long-lived animals should have more cancers than smaller/shorter-lived ones, due to increased number of cell divisions [3]. Actually, current evidence suggest that large/long-lived animals tend to have, on average, similar rates of cancer than small/short-lived ones [3]. A possible explanation for the absence of correlation, called Peto’s paradox [3, 22], is that evolution via natural selection may have played a significant role in shaping resistance mechanisms against malignant transformation in large/long-lived species [3, 23, 24]. Peto’s paradox postulates that animals that have evolved to be larger have also developed mechanisms to offset the increased risk of cancer. For example, some large vertebrate species have numerous copies of tumor suppressor genes (TSGs) [25], e.g. the elephant (Loxodonta africana) that has twelve orthologues of the human p53 gene, a key tumor suppressor fundamental to whole genome integrity. The role of natural selection is reinforced by the fact that Peto’s paradox seems not to exist at an intra-specific level, where taller individuals seem to have slightly more cancer than shorter ones [4, 16].

Although crucial to understand, this paradoxical relationship relies on a few over-simplistic assumptions (hereafter defined as Peto’s hypotheses): (i) the number of dividing-cells in an organism is strictly proportional to its size, (ii) each dividing cell has the same risk of mutation, and (iii) only mutations induce transformation to malignancy. Supporting evidence for Peto’s hypotheses is relatively scarce, mainly due to limited data on cancer prevalence in the wild [26], as well as owing to the fact that the existing evidence disproportionately focuses on certain organs and/or animal species.

The simplicity of these hypotheses cast doubts on how accurate/relevant/correct is Peto’s paradox in explaining cancer resistance, when there is clear deviation from theoretical expectations to empirical data when considering cancer prevalence in human and animal populations. Therefore, we review here Peto’s hypotheses listed above, through considering the complexity of carcinogenesis, as well as by focusing on oncogenic processes at different organismal levels: cells, organs and populations. We show that it is not only hard to accurately quantify the correctness of Peto’s assumptions, but also that the hypotheses are rarely valid, and therefore we propose to reconsider the legitimacy of Peto’s paradox. We discuss in details the potential ways to robustly assess the paradox, and argue that apart from body size, additional ecological, environmental and behavioral factors, together with the number of stem cells at the tissue/organismal levels should also be considered when assessing cancer prevalence, and attempting to identify species with resistance to cancer.

Discussion

Underlying hypotheses of Peto’s paradox

Do cell division patterns support Peto’s paradox?

The first hypothesis of Peto’s paradox postulates that large/long-lived animals have more dividing cells compared to smaller/short-lived ones. This hypothesis does not take into account the great variety of division rates within an organism where some cells could divide more frequently than others.

In many, if not most, cases, cancer may arise from transformation of stem cells [27], cells representing the first step of differentiation processes and with a great potential to divide (and/or proliferate). During the development of multicellular organisms, the obvious function of cell differentiation is to create new cell types. In adult organisms, new cell types are no longer needed or produced – but cell replacement is essential, tissues could be maintained by the self-duplication of fully mature and functional cells. Therefore, the function of ongoing, but tightly controlled cell differentiation may have evolved to protect from detrimental cell-level progression [28, 29]. With such a serial differentiation pattern, self-renewing cell populations are much more susceptible to somatic mutation, but these cells are rare and slow growing. Certain type of differentiated cells cannot initiate propagation of malignant phenotypes because they cannot divide, e.g. myocytes, adipocytes, and neurons [30]. Based on that concept, Peto’s hypothesis assumes that the number of stem cells should correlate with body mass. But the number of stem cells as well as the number of divisions have a low probability to correlate with body mass. A different number of differentiated cells may be obtained from the same number of stem cells [31] by dint of a switch between proliferation (dividing cell) and differentiation (non-dividing cell) (Fig. 2). Then, the number of divisions will not only depend on the number of stem cells, but also on the timing to switch between proliferation and differentiation (Fig. 2). The number of cells that will divide as well as the tissue turnover can be very different among organs [32], for example, in humans, the intestinal epithelium completely self-renews within ~ 5 days, while lung epithelium takes up to 6 months to be replaced [28]. Furthermore the number of stem cells is also different among organs, and this number could be involved in tumorigenesis [27]. Naively, one might think that having a larger organ requires a greater number of cells, but recent perspective papers show that differences of cell size could also be essential in determining organ size [33]. Including cell size as a parameter for the prediction of cancer risk shows that the correlation between body/organ size and cancer is weaker [33]. Furthermore, basal metabolic rate (BMR) is also decreased in larger animals compared to smaller ones (i.e. Max Kleiber allometric law [34]). Low BMR induces less oxidative stress in comparison to higher BMR [35]. Thus, larger animals could have a lower level of oxidative stress compared to smaller ones, and hence offsetting the higher cancer risk due to increased cell numbers. Indeed, a recent study by Dang, 2015 [36] support the hypothesis that metabolism can drive tumorigenesis and accounts for Peto’s paradox explanation.

Fig. 2
figure 2

Variation in time to switch between division and differentiation results in significant cell number differences inspite of the same starting stem cell numbers. a Stop of proliferation and start of differentiation after three generations lead to a larger differentiated tissue mass. b Stop of proliferation after one generation and start of differentiation earlier than A, result in a smaller differentiated tissue mass

Would transformation rates to cancer phenotypes be equivalent across different cell and tissue types?

Another assumption of Peto’s paradox, based on the fact that the rate of malignant transformation may be constant and similar across cell types, is that the mutation accumulation rate is constant among the cells. Important sources of genomic alterations are mutations, or spontaneous errors of DNA replication, [37, 38] that occur despite the existence of a wide range of mechanisms ensuring DNA repair and correct replication [39].

However, division processes – and mutation rates – may differ among cell types: for instance mutation rate has been reported to be 17 times higher in human somatic cells than in germ cells [40]. The mutation rate may differ also between organs, even though there is only limited data available on the mutational spectra of various tissue types [41]. Among differentiated cells, mutation rates of human retina cells has been estimated to be 3.7 times greater than intestinal epithelial cells, but still 1.48 times lower compared to that observed in lymphocytes [40] in which recombination events occur naturally and frequently. The rate of genetic alterations also varies across species, for example for a given organ, such as colon, mutation rates per generation is 2.14 times greater in the rat (Rattus norvegicus) than in the mouse (Mus musculus). The level of genetic variation can be intrinsic to the tissue type, e.g. the level of oxidative stress is very different across different tissue types [35]. Furthermore, mutation rates may also be affected by exposure to mutagens, especially in tissues, such as skin, respiratory and digestive epithelia, that are in direct contact with the external environment and then naturally more exposed to mutagens and radiations. Differences may also exist between similar organs in diverse animal species [40].

As suggested above, additional mechanisms, especially for lymphomas and leukemia, can increase DNA instability in specific cell types such as T and B lymphocytes, some of the key cells of the vertebrate immune system. One of the important characteristics of lymphocytes is that a specific part of their coding genome is hypermutated to generate the incredible genetic diversity necessary to recognize the plethora of foreign antigens, and hence protect the organism from a broad range of pathogens [42]. The enzymes involved in initiating the hypermutation events could potentially also increase the genomic instability of these cells and favor errors leading to lymphoid transformation [43].

Would carcinogenesis rely on mutations only?

The last assumption of Peto’s paradox is that a variety of somatic genomic alterations, from single nucleotide variants to larger structural aberrations (including insertions, deletions, and chromosomal translocations) can contribute to cell transformation (somatic mutation theory [44]). The genetic alterations will then be transmitted through DNA replication and cell division to the daughter cells. However, spontaneous mutations are insufficient to explain cell transformation in every situation [4547], and cancer can potentially also arise from a variety of other mechanisms, which may vary between organs and species (Table 1).

Table 1 Main cancer causes apart from that mentioned in Peto’s paradox

Variation in mutation numbers required to trigger tumor formation and progress

The number of genetic alterations varies largely, depending on age and tumor type, e.g. the number of genetic alterations is usually reduced in pediatric tumors such as juvenile myelomonocytic leukemia [48, 49] or acute megakaryoblastic leukemia [50] while being the highest in lung cancers induced by smoking [51] and melanomas induced by UV [52, 53]. The genomic signature of tumor cells (established based on the nature, localization and number of genomic alterations identified in the affected cells) informs about the factors that have promoted and contributed to the malignant transformation (ageing versus toxic exposure versus genetic predisposition etc…) [5457]. Solid tumors usually carry more genomic alterations than hematological malignancies [5860].

Furthermore, the functional consequences of a given mutation are highly variable, depending on its nature and localization in the genome. Those that have the most striking effects are those that activate a proto-oncogene (e.g. genes involved in cancer initiation/progression) or inactivate a tumor suppressor gene (e.g. genes that allow apoptosis or stop cell-cycle). A single nucleotide change can be sufficient to transform a proto-oncogene into an oncogene that induces cell transformation, whereas an inhibiting mutation must affect the two alleles of a tumor suppressor gene to favor transformation [61].

Epigenetic factors

In addition, a growing number of studies show that epigenetic stochasticity can act as driving force of carcinogenesis, via regulating the inhibition of tumor suppressor genes [62] as well as the activation of proto-oncogenes [63]. Since epigenetic stochasticity is not correlated to body size, it may introduce background noise when testing Peto’s paradox. Furthermore, since environmental factors (e.g. species ecology, habitat, resource availability) can significantly influence transgenerational epigenetic modifications, it can thus be important to consider both consistent and stochastic (e.g. oil spills, famine, extreme climate parameters) environmental changes across generations in order to decipher their contribution to tumor formation [62].

Tumor microenvironment

In addition to spontaneous mutation and epigenetic mechanisms, it is also increasingly recognized that tissue organization plays a major role in the development of malignant phenotypes (tissue organization field theory) [44]. This theory relies on the fact that cancer cells can proliferate only within a suitable microenvironment [1, 64], a particular tissue environment with specific conditions, e.g. low pH and/or oxygen concentrations [65]. Generally, normal tissue homeostasis and architecture inhibit progression of cancer, but changes in the microenvironment can shift the balance of these signals to a cancer permissive state. Tumor development, progression and metastasis are strongly dependent on the microenvironmental conditions met by cancer cells [1]. Tumor ecosystems consist of non-malignant normal cells (fibroblasts, immune cells and cells that comprise the blood vessels) and heterogeneous cancer cells, as well as their cellular products supporting cancer cell growth. Interactions between cancer cells and the surrounding microenvironment are constant, and bidirectional. Tumors can influence the microenvironment by releasing extracellular signals, promoting tumor angiogenesis and inducing peripheral immune tolerance. In return, the immune cells in the microenvironment influence the growth and evolution of cancerous cells (e.g. immune-editing [66]).

Animal models have demonstrated that alterations in the tissue microenvironment can promote the emergence of clonal malignancies, e.g. mutation in Dicer genes (involved in RNA interference) generated in the bone marrow microenvironment can promote the emergence of a leukemic clone [67, 68]. Lastly, the recent success of immunotherapeutic strategies demonstrates that suppression of the anticancer immune response is required for a tumor to emerge [69]. Therefore, even if cells have enough mutations to initiate carcinogenesis, malignant cells won’t develop without a permissive cancer niche and immune system, which will be then dependent of the tissue, the organ, and the species [65].

Thus, a Darwinian evolution of host factors relating to resistance may be more relevant for an explanation of Peto’s paradox, than carcinogenesis parameters such as cell divisions or stem cell number.

Peto’s paradox at the population level: artifact or reality?

Sampling bias

Assessment of Peto’s paradox [3, 4, 12, 20] relies on cancer incidence measured over very few species, i.e., dog (Canis lupus domesticus), mouse (Mus musculus), beluga (Delphinapterus leucas) and humans [12], covering a small gradient of the possible body mass. Another possible bias, when assessing this paradox, is that the detection of cancer relates only to the presence of macroscopic tumors, and thus neglects the precancerous lesions or the microscopic tumors of vital organs. Thus, due to the bias of studied species, current datasets are definitely lacking power to determine the exact relationship between body mass and cancer incidence [70].

Additionally, other sampling biases may also explain the lack of relationship between body mass and cancer prevalence. Of particular concern is that research so far has predominantly relied on domesticated and laboratory animals when attempting to establish the correlation. While the role of artificial selection for certain traits has been recognized [71], it seems to also apply to the emergence of cancer phenotypes. Anthropogenic selection (including domestication and breeding for particular traits in the laboratory) could have additionally led to artificial selection for cancer resistance or susceptibility. Therefore, laboratory and domesticated species, e.g., mice and dogs, could have cancer incidences different from wildlife species because of an inadvertent selection of traits involved directly or indirectly with carcinogenesis.

Environmental factors triggering the development of cancer phenotypes

Inter-species comparison can be challenging and misleading due to the fact that cancer initiating factors are probably not the same between different species. Indeed, comparison between human and other species could be biased by different levels and types of exposure to environmental and behavioral factors, including pollution, abundant and excess food supply, and frequent contact with mutagens [72, 73]. For instance, while there is no significant difference between body size of roe deer (Capreolus capreolus) and humans (on a logarithmic scale), cancer incidence is much higher in humans (20 % versus 2 % for roe deer) [7476]. These different incidences could be explained by physiological parameters, but also by a differential exposure to mutagens. Furthermore, human cancers have been studied more extensively and on a broader scale than the ones observed in wildlife, i.e., roe deer. Similarly, although extensive data is available on relatively high cancer prevalence in Belugas (27 %), these numbers originate from a pod of whales living in a polluted environment, suggesting that cancer prevalence could also be overestimated for this species, just like for humans [20]. For humans, the way of life may be critically important, for instance low concordance rate for leukemia in identical twins (5 %) suggests that additional postnatal exposure should influence leukemia development [77].

Comparing animal species occupying different trophic levels can also jeopardize the identification of animal species with resistance to cancer. For instance, mutation is also driven by cellular proliferation after injuries. Therefore, species with high injury rate from predators or aggressors should have evolved faster wound healing/tissue regeneration [78, 79], which could concomitantly increase the number of malignant transformations due to increased level of cell proliferation being associated with growth factors induced in tissue regeneration [80]. Furthermore, occupying different ecological niches can also contribute to various levels of cancer prevalence. For example, natural habitats of large mammals, such as elephants or beluga whales (except the aforementioned pod of whales), are significantly less polluted than the habitat of benthic organisms that are more exposed to contaminated sediments [81].

It is recognized that for many species longevity is highly correlated with size [82], but there are also noticeable exceptions, for instance the naked-mole rat that displays a maximum lifespan of 28.3 years for a mass of 35 g (in contrast to a similar size Mus musculus with a maximum lifespan of 3.5 years) [83]. Due to a long-lived organism potentially accumulating more mutations during its life [45, 84], it is expected that selection will favor cancer resistance in small, but long-lived species to circumvent the higher risk of cancer due to mutation accumulation (e.g. naked mole rate [85, 86]). Thus, for species displaying an atypical relationship between size and longevity, cancer resistance pattern will not follow the traditional prediction derived from Peto’s paradox.

Finally, increasing number of studies suggest that at least some cancers may have infectious origins [87]. The number of pathogen known to be associated with cancer in wildlife has also been on the rise, for example woodchucks (Marmota monax) suffering from hepatocarcinomas originating from hepatitis virus infections [88] and marine turtles succumbing to fibropapillomatosis also caused by viruses [89]. Several studies have focused on comparative analysis of parasite communities, and on the determining factors of parasite species richness, heterogeneity and densities [9092]. A relationship between body size and parasite species richness is thus possible, for example it has been shown that endogenous retroviruses abundance negatively correlates with body mass [93].

Summary

The disproportion and restricted nature of available data can make a paradox seemingly exist despite the actual lack of support for it. In this review, we have shown that the hypotheses behind Peto’s paradox are rarely supported by evidence, and therefore we question the relevance of using this paradox as a null hypothesis to identify selective pressures shaping cancer resistance mechanisms. Nevertheless, we emphasize that deciphering the relationship between ecological and behavioral parameters of animal species and cancer incidence can be essential and important to the identification of species which have evolved effective tumor resistance mechanisms. In addition, given the recent paper by Tomasetti and Vogelstein 2015 [27], we propose here that future research on Peto’s paradox should be envisaged from the number of stem cells per individuals/species rather than on the body size which seems to be an unreliable surrogate.

In this review, we have shown that having more cells does not necessarily mean increased number of malignant transformations, because different cell types have different division rates, and DNA mutations can accumulate at different frequencies through various mechanisms. Thus, each organ and each species should have different cancer prevalence. If organ size and tissue environment were equivalent across species, then the shortcomings of Peto’s hypotheses should not matter, and Peto’s paradox would remain valid. However, reality of animal species is obviously more complex due to physiological, ecological and evolutionary constraints of organisms.

Although Peto’s assumptions are not satisfied at cellular level, it is still possible to test Peto’s paradox across species by considering cancer in each organ separately. Due to individual organs having similar cellular structure and micro-environment across different species, a cross-species comparison of given organs would definitely be more informative, and would allow more rigorous and valid testing of Peto’s paradox.

However, the physiology of the organ should be considered carefully. For instance, only focusing on a digestive organ could lead to biased predictions due to the size of digestive organs being strongly influenced by diet (e.g. carnivore vs herbivore [9497]), the digestive tract of herbivores will be larger compared to carnivores, to allow an optimal digestion of cellulose [98].

Another possibility is to focus on the genome size. In fact, the variation observed in genome size across species could provide the foundations to the principles of Peto’s paradox (Animal Genome Size Database [99]): cancer incidence should be positively correlated with genome size rather than body size. A bigger genome should induce higher probability of mistakes in DNA replication during cell division, leading to higher risk of mutation and concomitantly to cancer. It has been proposed that extremely large genomes (like those of certain tree species) are an adaptation to withstand somatic mutations over the long haul, because of the mutagenic effects of pollutants, radiations or transposable elements are diluted [100] inside non-coding (and hence not harmful) junk DNA.

The philosophy of Peto’s paradox can be nevertheless applied at different scales. Indeed, within a given species, since each organ has its own tumor prevalence, one could propose the existence of higher cancer risk for larger organs [101] or, if Peto’s paradox exists at organ level, a lower cancer risk could be associated with resistance mechanisms driven by gene expression variations. For instance, pancreas size is conditioned by the initial number of progenitor cells. Therefore, size and cell number of this organ are fixed for the rest of the life, unlike the size/cell number of liver which could increase over a lifetime [102].

If Peto’s paradox could only be applied to organs, one should however also take into account that (i) the rate of regeneration of organs can vary between individuals depending on different exposure levels to mutagens (e.g. organs involved in removal of toxic materials (kidney), or organs in direct contact with external environment (digestive organs, lung)), (ii) the different mutation rates and (iii) the connections between the organs that may influence the spread of metastases by predetermined cellular pathways [103].

Conclusions

According to the different factors that may bias our interpretation of Peto’s paradox, comparing cancer prevalence across different species should take into account several fundamental parameters. Given that the assumptions of Peto’s paradox are not supported by strong evidence, our review suggests alternative ways for a more robust testing of the correlation (or rather lack of it) between body size and cancer risk. First, in view of great intra-individual variability in mutation and division rates across organs, it would be more appropriate to compare cancer prevalence in each organ separately [20]. Furthermore, since environmental factors can dramatically influence carcinogenesis, the integration of these factors would be essential to the accurate estimation of cancer prevalence across species. For an effective analysis, we suggest to compare species occupying similar ecological niches, or living in habitats where environmental factors can be controlled for, such as zoos or nature reserves.

We propose that refuting Peto’s paradox is actually not the most important question to be answered. Rather, investigating the lack of correlation between body mass and cancer incidence (the foundation of Peto’s paradox) opens up the opportunities to explore and answer such important queries as to how the random appearance of malignant cells influences cancer prevalence, and whether we could identify tumor resistance mechanisms without exploring entire genomes. The required next step is thus to estimate correctly this null hypothesis in order to interpret correctly this paradoxical relationship. Even if the three Peto’s hypotheses are flawed, it is crucial to determine whether the impact of discrepancies is enough to explain the lack of correlation between cancer risk and size/longevity at the interspecific level.

References

  1. Bissell M, Hines W. Why don’t we get more cancer? A proposed role of the microenvironment in restraining cancer progression. Nat Med. 2011;17:320–9.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  2. DeGregori J. Evolved tumor suppression: why are we so good at not getting cancer? Cancer Res. 2011;71:3739–44.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  3. Caulin AF, Maley CC. Peto’s Paradox: evolution’s prescription for cancer prevention. Trends Ecol Evol. 2011;26:175–82.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  4. Roche B, Hochberg ME, Caulin AF, Maley CC, Gatenby RA, Misse D, Thomas F. Natural resistance to cancers: a Darwinian hypothesis to explain Peto’s paradox. BMC Cancer. 2012;12:387-91.

  5. Stephens PJ, Tarpey PS, Davies H, Van Loo P, Greenman C, Wedge DC, et al. The landscape of cancer genes and mutational processes in breast cancer. Nature. 2012;486:400–04.

  6. Lee E, Iskow R, Yang L, Gokcumen O, Haseley P, Luquette III LJ, et al. Landscape of Somatic Retrotransposition in Human Cancers. Science. 2012;337:967–71.

  7. Kandoth C, McLellan MD, Vandin F, Ye K, Niu B, Lu C, et al. Mutational landscape and significance across 12 major cancer types. Nature. 2013;502:333–9.

  8. Stephens PJ, Tarpey PS, Davies H, Van Loo P, Greenman C, Wedge DC, et al. The landscape of cancer genes and mutational processes in breast cancer. Nature. 2012;486:400–4.

  9. Tian X, Azpurua J, Hine C, Vaidya A, Myakishev-Rempel M, Ablaeva J, et al. High-molecular-mass hyaluronan mediates the cancer resistance of the naked mole rat. Nature. 2013;499:346–9.

  10. Thomas F, Fisher D, Fort P, Marie J-P, Daoust S, Roche B, et al. Applying ecological and evolutionary theory to cancer: a long and winding road. Evol Appl. 2013;6:1–10.

  11. Galis F, Metz JAJ. Anti-cancer selection as a source of developmental and evolutionary constraints. Bioessays. 2003;25:1035–9.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  12. Leroi AM, Koufopanou V, Burt A. Cancer selection. Nat Rev Cancer. 2003;3:226–31.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  13. Domazet-Lošo T, Klimovich A, Anokhin B, Anton-Erxleben F, Hamm MJ, Lange C, et al. Naturally occurring tumours in the basal metazoan Hydra. Nat Commun. 2014;5:1–8.

  14. Squires D. Neoplasia in a Coral? Science (80-). 1965;148:503–5.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  15. Walker B, Figgs LW, Zahm SH. Differences in cancer incidence, mortality, and survival between African Americans and whites. Environ Health Perspect. 1995;103 Suppl (Table 2):275–81.

  16. Gunnell D, Smith GD, Holly J, Frankel S. Leg length and risk of cancer in the Boyd Orr cohort. BMJ. 1998;317:1350–1.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  17. Seluanov A, Hine C, Bozzella M. Distinct tumor suppressor mechanisms evolve in rodent species that differ in size and lifespan. Aging Cell. 2008;7:813–23.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  18. Andervont HB, Dunn TB. Occurrence of tumors in wild house mice. J Natl Cancer Inst. 1962;28:1153–63.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  19. Kim EB, Fang X, Fushan AA, Huang Z, Lobanov AV, Han L, et al. Genome sequencing reveals insights into physiology and longevity of the naked mole rat. Nature. 2011;479:223–7.

  20. Martineau D, Lemberger K, Dallaire A, Labelle P, Lipscomb TP, Michel P, et al. Cancer in wildlife, a case study: beluga from the St. Lawrence estuary, Québec, Canada. Environ Health Perspect. 2002;110:285–92.

  21. Roche B, Sprouffske K, Hbid H, Missé D, Thomas F. Peto’s paradox revisited: theoretical evolutionary dynamics of cancer in wild populations. Evol Appl. 2013;6:109–16.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  22. Peto R, Roe FJ, Lee PN, Levy L, Clack J. Cancer and ageing in mice and men. Br J Cancer. 1975;32:411–26.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  23. Graham J. Cancer Selection: The New Theory of Evolution. 1st edition. Aculeus; 1992.

  24. Nunney L. The real war on cancer: the evolutionary dynamics of cancer suppression. Evol Appl. 2013;6:11–9.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  25. Nunney L. Lineage selection and the evolution of multistage carcinogenesis. Proc Biol Sci. 1999;266:493–8.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  26. McAloose D, Newton AL. Wildlife cancer: a conservation perspective. Nat Rev Cancer. 2009;9:517–26.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  27. Tomasetti C, Vogelstein B. Variation in cancer risk among tissues can be explained by the number of stem cell divisions. Science (80-). 2015;347:78–81.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  28. Blanpain C, Horsley V, Fuchs E. Epithelial Stem Cells: Turning over New Leaves. Cell. 2007;128(3):445–58.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  29. Lander AD, Gokoffski KK, Wan FYM, Nie Q, Calof AL. Cell lineages and the logic of proliferative control. PLoS Biol. 2009;7:84-100.

  30. Iyama T, Wilson DM. DNA repair mechanisms in dividing and non-dividing cells. DNA Repair (Amst). 2013;12:620–36.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  31. Kavanagh K. Embedded molecular switches, anticancer selection, and effects on ontogenetic rates : A hypothesis of developmental constraint on morphogenesis and evolution. Evolution (N Y). 2003;57:939–48.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  32. Lui JC, Baron J. Mechanisms limiting body growth in mammals. Endocr Rev. 2011;32:422–40.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  33. Maciak S, Michalak P. Cell size and cancer: a new solution to Peto’s paradox? Evol Appl. 2015;8:2–8.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  34. Kleiber M. Body size and metabolic rate. Physiol Rev. 1947;27:511–41.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  35. Busuttil R, Garcia A, Reddick R. Intra-organ variation in age-related mutation accumulation in the mouse. PLoS One. 2007;9:1–10.

  36. Dang CV. A metabolic perspective of Peto’s paradox and cancer. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 2015;370:1-8.

  37. Friedberg EC, Wagner R, Radman M. Specialized DNA polymerases, cellular survival, and the genesis of mutations. Science. 2002;296:1627–30.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  38. Wodarz D. Effect of stem cell turnover rates on protection against cancer and aging. J Theor Biol. 2007;245:449–58.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  39. Su TT. Cellular responses to DNA damage: one signal, multiple choices. Annu Rev Genet. 2006;40:187–208.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  40. Lynch M. Evolution of the mutation rate. Trends Genet. 2010;26:345–52.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  41. Dollé ME, Snyder WK, Gossen JA, Lohman PH, Vijg J. Distinct spectra of somatic mutations accumulated with age in mouse heart and small intestine. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A. 2000;97:8403–8.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  42. Di Noia JM, Neuberger MS. Molecular mechanisms of antibody somatic hypermutation. Annu Rev Biochem. 2007;76:1–22.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  43. Vanasse GJ, Concannon P, Willerford DM. Regulated genomic instability and neoplasia in the lymphoid lineage. Blood. 1999;94:3997–4010.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  44. Soto AM, Sonnenschein C. The somatic mutation theory of cancer: growing problems with the paradigm? Bioessays. 2004;26:1097–107.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  45. DePinho R. The age of cancer. Nature. 2000;408:248–54.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  46. Jackson AL, Loeb LA. The mutation rate and cancer. Genetics. 1998;148:1483–90.

    CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  47. Busuttil R, Bahar R, Vijg J. Genome dynamics and transcriptional deregulation in aging. Neuroscience. 2007;145(4):1341–7.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  48. Loh ML, Sakai DS, Flotho C, Kang M, Fliegauf M, Archambeault S, et al. Mutations in CBL occur frequently in juvenile myelomonocytic leukemia. Blood. 2009;114:1859–63.

  49. Side BLE, Emanuel PD, Taylor B, Franklin J, Thompson P, Castleberry RP, et al. Mutations of the NF1 Gene in Children With Juvenile Myelomonocytic Leukemia Without Clinical Evidence of Neurofibromatosis, Type 1. Blood. 2014;1998:267–72.

  50. Loh ML, Mullighan CG. Advances in the genetics of high-risk childhood B-progenitor acute lymphoblastic leukemia and juvenile myelomonocytic leukemia: implications for therapy. Clin Cancer Res. 2012;18:2754–67.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  51. Mao L, Lee J, Kurie J. Clonal genetic alterations in the lungs of current and former smokers. J Natl Cancer Inst. 1997;89:857–62.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  52. Hocker T, Tsao H. Ultraviolet radiation and melanoma: A systematic review and analysis of reported sequence variants. Hum Mutat. 2007;28:578–88.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  53. Curtin JA, Fridlyand J, Kageshita T, Patel HN, Busam KJ, Kutzner H, et al. Distinct sets of genetic alterations in melanoma. N Engl J Med. 2005;353:2135–47.

  54. Matsumura Y, Ananthaswamy HN. Toxic effects of ultraviolet radiation on the skin. Toxicol Appl Pharmacol. 2004;195:298–308.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  55. Pleasance ED, Stephens PJ, O’Meara S, McBride DJ, Meynert A, Jones D, et al. A small-cell lung cancer genome with complex signatures of tobacco exposure. Nature. 2010;463:184–90.

  56. Bignell GR, Greenman CD, Davies H, Butler AP, Edkins S, Andrews JM, et al. Signatures of mutation and selection in the cancer genome. Nature. 2010;463:893–8.

  57. Alexandrov LB, Nik-Zainal S, Wedge DC, Aparicio SA, Behjati S, Biankin AV, et al. Signatures of mutational processes in human cancer. Nature. 2013;500:415–21.

  58. Komarova NL, Sengupta A, Nowak MA. Mutation-selection networks of cancer initiation: Tumor suppressor genes and chromosomal instability. J Theor Biol. 2003;223:433–50.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  59. Vogelstein B, Kinzler KW. Cancer genes and the pathways they control. Nat Med. 2004;10:789–99.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  60. Nowell PC. Tumor progression: A brief historical perspective. Semin Cancer Biol. 2002;12(4):261–6.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  61. Knudson A. Two genetic hits (more or less) to cancer. Nat Rev Cancer. 2001;1:637–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  62. Feinberg AP. Epigenetic stochasticity, nuclear structure and cancer: the implications for medicine. J Intern Med. 2014;276:5–11.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  63. Wolffe A, Matzke M. Epigenetics: Regulation through repression. Science (80-). 1999;286:481–6.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  64. Whiteside TL. The tumor microenvironment and its role in promoting tumor growth. Oncogene. 2008;27:5904–12.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  65. Barcellos-Hoff MH, Lyden D, Wang TC. The evolution of the cancer niche during multistage carcinogenesis. Nat Rev Cancer. 2013;13:511–8.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  66. Pardoll DM. The blockade of immune checkpoints in cancer immunotherapy. Nat Rev Cancer. 2012;12:252–64.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  67. Purizaca J, Meza I, Pelayo R. Early lymphoid development and microenvironmental cues in B-cell acute lymphoblastic leukemia. Arch Med Res. 2012;43:89–101.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  68. Askmyr M, Quach J, Purton LE. Effects of the bone marrow microenvironment on hematopoietic malignancy. Bone. 2011;48:115–20.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  69. Schreiber RD, Old LJ, Smyth MJ. Cancer immunoediting: integrating immunity’s roles in cancer suppression and promotion. Science. 2011;331(i):1565–70.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  70. Nagy JD, Victor EM, Cropper JH. Why don’t all whales have cancer? A novel hypothesis resolving Peto’s paradox. Integr Comp Biol. 2007;47:317–28.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  71. Reissmann M, Ludwig A. Pleiotropic effects of coat colour-associated mutations in humans, mice and other mammals. Semin Cell Dev Biol. 2013;24:576–86.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  72. Willett WC. Diet and cancer. Oncologist. 2000;5:393–404.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  73. Epstein S. Environmental Determinants of Human Cancer. Cancer Res. 1974;34(10):2425–35.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  74. Aguirre AA, Bröjer C, Mörner T. Descriptive epidemiology of roe deer mortality in Sweden. J Wildl Dis. 1999;35:753–62.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  75. Bishop J. Viruses, genes and cancer. Amer Zool. 1989;29:653–66.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  76. Muirhead CR, Kendall GM, Darby SC, Doll R, Haylock RGE, O’Hagan JA, et al. Epidemiological studies of UK test veterans: II. Mortality and cancer incidence. J Radiol Prot. 2004;24:219–41.

  77. Mori H, Colman SM, Xiao Z, Ford AM, Healy LE, Donaldson C, et al. Chromosome translocations and covert leukemic clones are generated during normal fetal development. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A. 2002;99:8242–7.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  78. Fernandez AA. A cancer-causing gene is positively correlated with male aggression in Xiphophorus cortezi. J Evol Biol. 2010;23:386–96.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  79. Archie EA, Altmann J, Alberts SC. Social status predicts wound healing in wild baboons. Proc Natl Acad Sci. 2012;109(23):9017–22.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  80. Aktipis CA, Nesse RM. Evolutionary foundations for cancer biology. Evol Appl. 2013;6:144–59.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  81. Black JJ, Baumann PC. Carcinogens and cancers in freshwater fishes. Environ Health Perspect. 1991;90:27–33.

  82. Speakman JR. Body size, energy metabolism and lifespan. J Exp Biol. 2005;208(Pt 9):1717–30.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  83. Pérez V, Buffenstein R, Masamsetti V, Leonard S, Salmon AB, Mele J, et al. Protein stability and resistance to oxidative stress are determinants of longevity in the longest-living rodent, the naked mole-rat. Proc Natl Acad Sci. 2009,106:1–6.

  84. Kirkwood TBL, Austad SN. Why do we age? Nature. 2000;408(6809):233–8.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  85. Faulkes CG, Davies KTJ, Rossiter SJ, Benette NC. Molecular evolution of the hyaluronan synthase 2 gene in mammals: implications for adaptations to the subterranean niche and cancer resistance. Biol Lett. 2015;11(5):20150185.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  86. Keane M, Craig T, Alfoldi J, Berlin AM, Johnson J, Seluanov A, et al. The Naked Mole Rat Genome Resource: facilitating analyses of cancer and longevity-related adaptations. Bioinformatics. 2014;30:3558–60.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  87. Ewald PW. An Evolutionary Perspective on Parasitism as a Cause of Cancer. Advances in Parasitology. 2009;68:21-43. 

  88. Menne S, Cote PJ. The woodchuck as an animal model for pathogenesis and therapy of chronic hepatitis B virus infection. World J Gastroenterol. 2007;13:104–24.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  89. Aguirre AA, Lutz P. Marine Turtles as Sentinels of Ecosystem Health: Is Fibropapillomatosis an Indicator? EcoHealth. 2004;1:275-83.

  90. Guégan F, Lambert A, Lévêque C, Combes C, Euzet L. Can host body size explain the parasite species richness in tropical freshwater fishes ? Oecologia. 1992;90:197–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  91. Morand S, Poulin R. Density, body mass and parasite species richness of terrestrial mammals. Evol Ecol. 1998;12:217-27.

  92. Lindenfors P, Nunn CL, Jones KE, Cunningham AA, Sechrest W, Gittleman JL. Parasite species richness in carnivores: effects of host body mass, latitude, geographical range and population density. Glob Ecol Biogeogr. 2007;16:496–509.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  93. Katzourakis A, Magiorkinis G, Lim AG, Gupta S, Belshaw R, Gifford R. Larger mammalian body size leads to lower retroviral activity. PLoS Pathog. 2014;10:e1004214.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  94. Barnes G, Vernon T. Digestive organ morphology, diet, and guild structure of North American Anatidae. Can J Zool. 1987;65:1812–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  95. O’Grady SP, Morando M, Avila L, Dearing MD. Correlating diet and digestive tract specialization: examples from the lizard family Liolaemidae. Zoology (Jena). 2005;108:201–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  96. Aiello LC, Wheeler P. The expensive-tissue hypothesis. Curr Anthropol. 2014;36:199–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  97. Kehoe P, Ankney D. Variation in digestive organ size among five species of diving ducks (Aythya spp.). Can J Zool. 1985;63:2339–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  98. Hume I. Digestive strategies of mammals. Acta Zoologica Sinica. 2002;48:1-19.

  99. Gregory TR, Nicol JA, Tamm H, Kullman B, Kullman K, Leitch IJ, et al. Eukaryotic genome size databases. Nucleic Acids Res. 2007;35:D332–8.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  100. Petrov DA. Evolution of genome size: new approaches to an old problem. Trends Genet. 2001;17:23–8.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  101. Albanes D, Winick M. Are Cell Numver and Cell Proliferation Risk Factores for Cancer? J Natl Cancer Inst. 1988;80:772–5.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  102. Stanger BZ, Tanaka AJ, Melton DA. Organ size is limited by the number of embryonic progenitor cells in the pancreas but not the liver. Nature. 2007;445:886–91.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  103. Vanharanta S, Massagué J. Origins of Metastatic Traits. Cancer Cell. 2013;24:410–21.

  104. Petrucelli N, Daly MB, Feldman GL. Hereditary breast and ovarian cancer due to mutations in BRCA1 and BRCA2. Genet Med. 2010;12:245–59.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  105. Boffetta P. Human cancer from environmental pollutants: the epidemiological evidence. Mutat Res. 2006;608:157–62.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  106. Pope III CA. Lung cancer, cardiopulmonary mortality, and long-term exposure to fine particulate Air pollution. JAMA. 2002;287(9):1132–41.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  107. Calle EE, Rodriguez C, Walker-Thurmond K, Thun MJ. Overweight, obesity, and mortality from cancer in a prospectively studied cohort of U.S. adults. N Engl J Med. 2003;348:1625–38.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  108. Hursting SD, Nunez NP, Varticovski L, Vinson C. The obesity-cancer link: lessons learned from a fatless mouse. Cancer Res. 2007;67:2391–3.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work was funded by the ANR (Evocan Research project), the CNRS, SPALLIAN and NEMAUSYS.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Authors’ contributions

HD, BR and FT have designed the study. BU, ES, DM, NP, FB, AA, MV, FB, FR, HD, BR and FT have contributed to different parts of the manuscript. All authors have significantly contributed to the manuscript and approved the final version.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ducasse, H., Ujvari, B., Solary, E. et al. Can Peto’s paradox be used as the null hypothesis to identify the role of evolution in natural resistance to cancer? A critical review. BMC Cancer 15, 792 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1186/s12885-015-1782-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s12885-015-1782-z

Keywords